Items related to The Trial and Death of Socrates: Four Dialogues

The Trial and Death of Socrates: Four Dialogues - Softcover

 
9781452847139: The Trial and Death of Socrates: Four Dialogues
View all copies of this ISBN edition:
 
 
The Trial and Death of Socrates: Four Dialogues , written by legendary author Plato, is widely considered to be one of the greatest classic texts of all time. This great classic will surely attract a whole new generation of readers. For many, The Trial and Death of Socrates: Four Dialogues is required reading for various courses and curriculums. And for others who simply enjoy reading timeless pieces of classic literature, this gem by Plato is highly recommended. Published by Classic Books International and beautifully produced, The Trial and Death of Socrates: Four Dialogues would make an ideal gift and it should be a part of everyone's personal library.

"synopsis" may belong to another edition of this title.

About the Author:
Plato was born to an aristocratic Athenian family in 427 BC, became an adherent of the already notorious arguer Socrates in his youth, and likely abandoned Athens for several years following Socrates’ execution in 399 BC. Back in Athens, he founded his infamous school, the Academy, on his estate of the same name, probably in the 360s. Plato’s sweeping and multifaceted philosophy, as documented in his voluminous writings, has never ceased to exert a remarkably pervasive influence upon the intellectual culture of the West.
Excerpt. © Reprinted by permission. All rights reserved.:

Introduction

 

The dialogues of Plato stand alongside the Bible and Homer’s Iliad and Odyssey as foundational texts of Western civilization. The works of Plato collected under the title The Trial and Death of Socrates have been particularly influential because they provide both an excellent point of entry into Plato’s vast philosophy and a strikingly vivid portrait of Plato’s mentor, Socrates – one of the most uncompromising intellectuals in the pantheon of human history and culture. While arguments presented in some of Plato’s other dialogues add essential dimensions to our understanding of his thought, it is possible to find the core elements of Plato’s system in Euthyphro, Apology, Crito, and Phaedo, and it is predominantly through Plato’s account in these works of the words and actions of Socrates during his trial and execution for impiety that the latter’s nobility and profound integrity have become known to succeeding generations.

 

Plato was born to an aristocratic Athenian family in 427 BC, became an adherent of the already notorious arguer Socrates in his youth, and likely abandoned Athens for several years following Socrates’ execution in 399 BC. Back in Athens, he founded his infamous school, the Academy, on his estate of the same name, probably in the 360s. Though the curriculum of Plato’s Academy changed significantly during the years after his death, the school itself remained an important center of learning until AD 529, when the Eastern Roman Emperor dissolved it during a purge of non-Christian institutions. There is no consensus on precisely when or why Plato began writing the incomparably thought-provoking collection of dialogues and letters that has come down to us. Some commentators suggest that his earliest writings were set down prior to Socrates’ execution as aids to the memory of those who witnessed or participated in the latter’s arguments, while many others believe that it was Socrates’ death that stimulated Plato to begin documenting for posterity the intellectual achievements of his friend and teacher. In any event, Plato’s sweeping and multifaceted philosophy, as documented in his voluminous writings, has never ceased to exert a remarkably pervasive influence upon the intellectual culture of the West. It decisively shaped the thought of St. Augustine (AD 354 - 386) and through him infiltrated virtually all subsequent Christian theology. Moreover, from ancient times until the present, there have been few great Western thinkers – religious or secular – who have failed to acknowledge an unparalleled debt to Plato.

 

It is customary to divide Plato’s dialogues into early, middle, and late periods. In the early writings it is believed that Plato was strongly under Socrates’ influence and, therefore, that the characterization of Socrates’ thought and method of discourse in these so-called “Socratic dialogues” accurately reflects Plato’s recollections of his teacher. In Plato’s middle period, Socrates is made the spokesman for a philosophy that notably differs from anything articulated in the early writings. Here it is suspected that Plato is setting forth his own philosophy – one that grew out of reflection upon unresolved dilemmas raised by Socrates’ philosophical activity and by the traumatic experience of Socrates’ untimely demise. This middle-period philosophy can be viewed as Plato’s effort to produce a defense of Socrates’ virtue and a metaphysical system explaining the structure of a reality in which a good and just man can be executed for publicly seeking the truth. In the late writings, the metaphysics of the middle period is subjected to withering criticism and, though not jettisoned, recognized as seriously problematic. Of the four dialogues in the present volume, Euthyphro, Apology, and Crito are all widely agreed to belong to the early period. Phaedo, conversely, is regarded as belonging to the middle period or as a transitional work marking the beginning of the middle period. This is of importance because it provides insight into what is taking place in The Trial and Death of Socrates in the subtext of Socrates approaching his trial for impiety and corrupting the youth (Euthyphro), giving an unsuccessful defense (Apology), rejecting an offer to escape Athens before his execution (Crito), and, on his final day, discussing the merits of belief in an afterlife and then drinking his poison (Phaedo).

 

Socrates, the central figure in most of Plato’s dialogues, left no written record of his ideas. The image we have of him is almost entirely the product of his depiction by Plato, though he also figures prominently in the dialogues of Xenophon and other contemporary authors and is caricatured in Aristophanes’ play The Clouds. And though, in the last analysis, it is Plato’s “Socrates” who has influenced mankind through the ages and with whom we are rightfully concerned, we should be aware that other sources give alternative accounts of Socrates’ character, beliefs, and actions, and that the historical veracity of Plato’s depiction is doubtful.

 

The events of Socrates’ life, however, take place against a well-documented historical background, though this is largely left implicit in Plato’s writings. What is most essential for the reader to know about this background is that Socrates’ native city-state, Athens, was once ancient Greece’s flagship democracy. Despite the facts that the right of citizenship was granted only to a fraction of Athenian inhabitants and that during Socrates’ lifetime the Athenian democracy succumbed twice to the rule of tyrannical oligarchs, the onetime power and prosperity of democratic Athens signaled a major political innovation in the ancient world. Coinciding with the rise of democracy in Greece came an increasing prioritization of oratory skills. For in the agora, where citizens met to decide upon the affairs of state, the majority needed to be persuaded of appropriate courses of action. And so, in the century prior to Socrates’ execution, traveling teachers of a peculiar type of oratory began to appear. These teachers, famously known as “Sophists,” received payment for teaching prominent aristocratic youths techniques for winning arguments, regardless of the correctness of the arguer’s position, and thus they were widely regarded as parasites and public nuisances. This is an important point in relationship to the narrative of The Trial and Death of Socrates because though Socrates was officially accused of impiety and corrupting Athenian youth with his blasphemous ideas, his defense in the Apology consists essentially of a denial that he was a Sophist – something with which he was not explicitly charged.

 

In Euthyphro we find Socrates, on the way to his trial, pausing to engage in his typical form of inquiry with a theologian named Euthyphro, who claims to know with certainty the nature of “piety” or “holiness.” Socrates’ method is to pose to Euthyphro the question, “What is piety?” and when Euthyphro offers an answer, to ask him probing questions about it until he retreats. Once again, Socrates asks, “What is piety?” A new answer is offered, and the cycle begins again. Ultimately this leads Euthyphro – as it did many of Socrates interlocutors – to give up and slip away. This portrayal of Socrates’ activity coincides with what Aristotle – a student at the Academy during the last two decades of Plato’s life – has to say about it: “Socrates was occupying himself with the excellences of character, and in connection with them became the first to raise the problem of universal definition. . .two things may be fairly ascribed to Socrates – inductive arguments and universal definitions, both of which are concerned with the starting-point of [knowledge].” The first observation to make here about the agreement between Aristotle’s comments on Socrates and the latter’s depiction in Euthyphro (and other early dialogues) is Socrates’ preoccupation with “excellences of character,” i.e., with morality. Thus the inquiry here is about piety, and in other early dialogues it is about virtues such as justice, courage, and temperance. The next point is that what Socrates seeks as a valid answer to his question “What is piety?” is a universal definition, not an example or even a whole collection of examples of piety. Socrates’ criteria for a valid definition are implicit in his objections to Euthyphro’s answers: It must be the characteristic which is the same in all instances of the thing inquired about; it must be the distinguishing characteristic marking those things off from other things; it must be the “essence” of those things – i.e., that which makes them be what they are – and as such, a standard by which one could measure whether or not something was an example of this kind of thing. Lastly, Aristotle credits Socrates with inventing inductive argument in the course of his search for the starting-point of knowledge, and in Euthyphro and other early dialogues Socrates’ inquiries begin with a truth claim and work backward to find the basis upon which this claim rests. Only if such a basis could be discover...

"About this title" may belong to another edition of this title.

(No Available Copies)

Search Books:



Create a Want

If you know the book but cannot find it on AbeBooks, we can automatically search for it on your behalf as new inventory is added. If it is added to AbeBooks by one of our member booksellers, we will notify you!

Create a Want

Other Popular Editions of the Same Title

9780486270661: The Trial and Death of Socrates: Four Dialogues (Dover Thrift Editions: Philosophy)

Featured Edition

ISBN 10:  0486270661 ISBN 13:  9780486270661
Publisher: Dover Publications, 1992
Softcover

  • 9781494846831: The Trial and Death of Socrates: Four Dialogues

    Create..., 2013
    Softcover

Top Search Results from the AbeBooks Marketplace